Engaging with Oliver Burkeman: towards a Christian ‘antidote’

When visiting the local Waterstones, and other bookshops, I tend to take a quick glance at the section of the shelves variously marked ‘Mind, Body, Spirit’, ‘Spirituality’ or ‘Self Help’.  That often includes ‘religion’, though I’ve been struck recently by the declining shelf space occupied by Christian material.

My impression is that people are drawn to Christianity sometimes as a result of life problems with which they lacked the resources to deal.  So, I’m naturally curious about which ‘life problems’ currently head the popular agenda, as well as the philosophical or religious basis of the solutions being offered by the books on sale.  I guess, underlying this interest, is a conviction that Christianity, unfashionable though it has become, really ought to have something to offer in this department.

Maybe it was some such interest that motivated Elisabeth Oldfield of the Theos Think Tank, in her recent excellent podcast, to interview Guardian columnist and best-selling self help author, Oliver Burkeman.  She claims on the video to have been drawn by his manner of using people’s everyday life problems as a way of ‘burrowing down’ into deep philosophical and religious issues. 

At all events, all this signalled to me a good opportunity for Christian cultural engagement. So, I duly bought and read Burkeman’s most recent book – The Antidote: Happiness for People Who Can’t Stand Positive Thinking. I was not disappointed.

The problem with positive thinking ….

What is the ‘antidote’ of the title? The word suggests a medication to counteract a venom or poison. The venom, in this case could be either ‘positive thinking’ itself, or it could be the ethos of ‘intolerance of uncertainty’ and ‘insecurity’ which, according to Burkeman positive thinking seeks to address.

It is the first of these which, on the face of it, offers the structuring idea that holds the book together. The first chapter reports the author’s visit to ‘America’s most popular motivational seminar’ (a chapter almost as boring as the event described, despite the author’s best efforts at humorous treatment).  Subsequent chapters (like their subject matter, vastly more entertaining) focus, in the familiar journalisty way, on a personal ‘story’, emanating largely from an interview or the author’s own experience somehow relating in a negative fashion to positive thinking and its mania for setting personal goals (goalaholicism).  For example, Stoic ‘negative visualization’, presented for us through an interview with the UK’s foremost contemporary Stoic, Dr Keith Seddon, offers us the antithesis of the ‘positive visualization’ dear to Tony Robbins; a lively report of the author’s own participation in an Insight Meditation Society retreat demonstrates the aim of the properly Buddhist practice to be a spiritual ‘detachment’ evidently incompatible with goalaholicism; an interview with ‘the world’s bestselling living ‘spiritual’ author, Ulrich (now Eckhart) Tolle even throws into doubt the very existence of that ‘self’ Robert Schuller would have us setting our goals for.  And so on.

But does the book also purport to be an ‘antidote’ in addressing the underlying problems to which positive thinking provides so evidently spurious an answer? Does it offer anything in the way of an alternative solution? 

Actually, you can’t say much about Stoicism or the true end of Buddhist meditation without getting into some serious thinking – and Burkeman yields happily enough to the temptation.  The reader soon discerns a distinctive authorial angle on the issues considered. This from time to time expands into reflections of a philosophical and religious nature which reveal sufficient consistency over the book to entitle us, I think, to speak of a philosophical and religious perspective that is recognisable enough.  If I had to encapsulate the essence of this position, I could do worse than proffer, in response, the name of the great sixties prophet of the ‘spiritual but not religious’, Alan Watts.

Watts might even have been as appropriate an interlocutor as Oliver Burkeman for the purposes of the present piece.  Be that as it may, I make no apology if the remainder of this blog gives an impression of addressing the high-priest of self-help spirituality through the intermediary of his living disciple. 

Here, then, is the philosophy (whether of Watts or Burkeman, I’m not sure) as presented in passages scattered through the chapters of The Antidote

The ‘self’ and its discontents

The first and longest concerns a challenge that Watts sets his readers – to define where ‘self’ ends and ‘everything else’ begins.  This turns out to be less than straightforward.  For a start, it is by no means obvious where such a boundary should be placed.  Should our relationships be considered an aspect of what makes us who we are; or are they part of the ‘out there’ which we inhabit?  And what about the communities in which we belong, or even the things that constitute our physical environment?  Would we truly be what we are, without them?  And so on.

More fundamentally, we will become aware of a certain arbitrariness about the very notion of a boundary:

… it doesn’t make much sense to describe a boundary as something that keeps two things apart.  It makes more sense to describe it as the place at which they meet – or more accurately, the place at which they are exactly the same thing.  The inside of the boundary relies for its very existence on the outside, and vice versa; they are, inextricably and by definition, part of the same whole … the self is best thought of as some kind of a fiction …. (pp. 121-2).

Now this most fundamental of realizations, says B., can help us understand why attempts to achieve happiness through the ‘optimism-focused, goal-fixated, positive-thinking approach to happiness’ are doomed to frustration.  To see precisely why, we need to step back a couple of chapters to the account that B. gives us of the week he once spent at a retreat with the Insight Meditation Society.

Burkeman’s observations on this experience are so helpful in delineating his own position, and so revealing of both its strength and its limitations, that I make no excuse for appearing to embark on what may seem a digression, at this point. Their relevance relevance to our argument will shortly become clear.

So let us consider that experience.

Participants in the retreat, he tells us, were instructed to focus on their breathing.  In the words of the instructor: ‘”Physical sensations, feelings and thoughts will carry us away into distraction.  In meditation, when we notice that happening, we don’t judge.  We just return to the breath.”  It was really that simple, apparently’, B. goes on.  Needless to say, ‘simple’ doesn’t mean ‘easy’, as becomes apparent from what follows in B.’s account.  Yet, by the end of the retreat, something has happened:

My constant efforts to return to focussing on my breath – to avoid becoming attached to thoughts or emotions – seemed to be having an effect.  My vantage point on my mental activity had altered, as if I’d climbed two rungs up a stepladder in order to observe from above. … Much of my thinking concerned the past or the future, but I was no longer being yanked off into daydreams or unpleasant memories; I was absolutely present, there on the cushion, watching the performance with something less like panic and more like interest.

The meditator has become aware of a separation between their ‘vantage point’ as meditator and their own thoughts and feelings.  In more philosophical terms, the ‘subject’ (i.e. that ‘whatever-it-is’ constituting the ‘vantage point’) is revealed to be non-identical with ‘self’ or ‘ego’.

Now this is the realization that B. brings to the critique of ‘goal-fixated’ positive-thinking.  Whereas meditation is about ‘disidentifying’ from our own mental projections of ourselves, positive-thinking is all about identifying with them.  We ‘fortify’ the boundaries of the self by ‘asserting superiority over others, as if we could separate ourselves from them’.  It is easy to see why this is futile and self-defeating, given that what is being asserted here (i.e. the self) is ultimately fictional.  In short, ‘goal-fixated’ positive-thinking is, in B’s view, chasing the wind.  It risks drawing us into a vicious loop whereby the tighter our clasp on ‘reality’, the more it will seem to elude us.

So much then for the philosophical ‘antidote’ Burkeman and Watts appear to be offering us.

What do we make of it?

Is ‘self’ really the problem?

Broadly, there are some aspects that seem to me sound, others I find hard to accept.

Among the first, most important is that sense B. derives from his experience of Buddhist meditation of the ‘subject’ existing independently of the ‘self’ or ‘ego’.  It also follows from B.’s reflection on that experience – as from the more theoretical kind of introspection we find in existentialist philosophy – that the ‘subject’ and the ‘reality’ of its experience exist in co-dependency with each other.  By this I mean that ‘reality’ – at least as we humans know it – can only be apprehended from the vantage point of an experiencing subject; and, conversely, that human subjectivity is thinkable only in relation to a world that opens up to it. 

However, I would disagree with the next move in their argument, namely, that, if the subject and its reality are mutually co-dependent, therefore ‘they are exactly the same thing’; or that, because the notion of a boundary between subject and reality depends on it having two sides, such a boundary has only a notional existence.  Why, in principle, couldn’t two things be ‘inextricably and by definition, part of the same whole’, yet NOT reducible to one another!

The reason, I believe, has to do with a confusion in mind of Burkeman and Watts between two distinct things: namely, the ‘subject’, and the ‘self’/‘ego’ of its projections.  It is perfectly true, of course, that the self (an object in our world like anything else) cannot easily be distinguished from the non-self.  But there is no reason to suppose that this same indistinguishability also applies to the relationship between the subject and its world.  In fact, the lesson to be drawn from B.’s meditation experience is precisely that the subject IS in essence separable from the self of our conscious projections.  In fact, it is precisely this realization that then enables us to recognize the inseparability of self and non-self.  Without that realization, subject and self remain intertwined. As a result, the fundamental ‘over-and-against-ness’ of the subject is imputed also to the self, thus driving that tendency B. observes for us to ‘fortify’ our egos.

There is another aspect of B.’s argument that I cannot accept.  This is that self and ego are any more ‘fictional’, or less real, for not being identical with the subject.  The reasoning of Descartes, which constitutes a point of departure for Burkeman’s discussion, happens to offer an interesting case of precisely the opposite conclusion. Descartes’ reasons from the apperception of the ‘cogito’ (the undeniable reality of the ‘I’ that thinks, or, at least, of the act of thinking that goes on) to the evident reality of those other phenomena of his world which offer themselves to our ‘clear and distinct’ reasonings.  While B. argues from the unreality of the self and its projects to the unreality of everything else (hence for a policy of acquiescence in the transience of life), Descartes moves from its evident reality to the reality of things in the world.  All things considered, I cannot see why the co-dependency of subject and reality should lead us to conclude anymore to the unreality of both terms than to their reality. 

Certainly, if durability in time is a criterion, there appear aspects of the self that would seem more long-lasting and more rooted in the past than the subject.  Social identity, culture and language, through their reproduction and transmission down the generations, would seem to achieve considerable durability.  Cultural systems are all sustained through a struggle against natural transience; indeed, human civilization, taken in aggregate, would seem a remarkably successful effort to achieve a degree of permanence over time – a more or less effectual, if spatio-temporally very localized, resistance to the Second Law of Thermodynamics.  In fact, if you want fully to weigh up what that overall human project means for our sense of self – try, as a thought-experiment, to take imaginatively fully on board the notion of an imminent and certain extinction of humanity – or even just of our cultural tradition.  Our sense of self can indeed survive the prospect of personal death, but the very thought of a final catastrophe instantly turns out the light on any human meaning and value.,

So, how do these concerns relate to what B.’s book is saying?  Do they detract in any way from its value?

Not altogether.  B. adduces various interesting and amusing examples of where the fixation on goals, so characteristic of positivity culture, can turn out to be counter-productive.  It is surely true, that, as Steve Shapiro comments ‘you can have a broad sense of direction without a specific goal, or precise vision of the future’.  Given the uncertainties the future presents, there may be much to be said, in many contexts, for the more improvisatory strategy of ‘meandering with purpose’.   Yet, even if precise goals have their place in business planning, the transformation of such strategies into principles for the conduct of our private lives will have implications for our attitudes to failure, uncertainty and insecurity, that hardly be conducive to personal contentment.

That said, the fundamental aspiration, and even need, to ‘control the future’ is surely common to all human projects, collective as much as individual.  It is our human lot to struggle for order in the world – even if perfectionism, the denial of past failures, or an overly narrow focus on very specific goals, turn out to be strategies poorly adapted for success in that struggle. Hence the only alternative to a self clearly defined over-and-against its world, is disengagement from worldly projects.  There are doubtless benefits to a degree of temporary disengagement – as a temporary strategy for challenging our narrow self-definition, perhaps, or, for expanding our definition of self.  Yet, the ultimate purpose of these exercises remains the re-established engagement of an expanded self with broader projects, not a continuation of the disengagement.  Even in the case of the greatest conceivable expansion of our definition of self, that self must remain a ‘self’ (and as such distinct from the subject).  And the purpose ultimately served thereby would be an expansion of self and its engagements, not its elimination.

So, I am suspicious of those more philosophical aspects of B.’s critique of positive thinking that rely on the kind of existential analysis promoted by the likes of Alan Watts, Eckhart Tolle, or Ernest Becker.  I do not believe the self to be a ‘fiction’ – not even a ‘useful’ one.  Yes, it is a social/cultural ‘construct’ – but that is a very different claim.

This leaves us with the question – since the struggle to control the future and maintain self-definition is unavoidable – whether the specific construction of self we find in positivity culture is indeed so unusually prone to ‘insecurity’ and ‘intolerance of certainty’.  If so, then why?

A very modern kind of ‘self’

That was the question going around in my head, as I went to bed one evening.  To my surprise, I woke up about 4 am the following morning clutching at what seemed like an answer.  On this occasion, that answer turned out to be no mere figment of my dreams, but an apparently sensible, if by no means immediately obvious, connection with a train of ideas I had been pursuing for some time in a rather different enquiry.

I am referring here to the notion of self that we find evoked most famously by Charles Taylor in his various explorations of the contemporary culture of expressivist individualism.  Actually, this is a very different meaning of self from the one I have assumed in the above paragraphs.  Taylor’s concept is an ideological – or, more properly, I should say, ideational – one, and is consequently quite specific to what Taylor considers to be the dominant worldview of the contemporary age: namely, expressivist individualism.   To avoid confusion, I shall henceforth use a capital letter (Self) to distinguish this ideational meaning of self from the more general one.

Already, my reading of The Antidote had led me to reflect on a range of terms – ‘ego’, ‘first person’, ‘self’, ‘subject’ – seemingly being deployed by B. as potential synonyms in relation that/those ill-defined entit(ies).  What occurred to me at 4am that morning related to one potential consequence of such terminological ambiguity.  Maybe, I thought, it was the specific understanding of self as ‘Self’ rather than the more general explanations of Watts or Tolle that lay at the existential basis of extreme contemporary attitudes to insecurity and intolerance, especially in positivity culture.  On reflection it became clear to me that this was most certainly the case.      

To explain my conviction, I need to say something about expressivist individualism, and the very specific understanding of self (i.e. as Self) that it tends to produce.

Broadly, much contemporary culture (including positive thinking) defines Self as something ‘inward’ and uniquely precious to each one of us which we discover through its expression in the world.  Expressivist individualism is the belief that such ‘self-fulfilment’ or ‘self-realization’ constitutes the ultimate source of value and the ultimate human good.  Not only does this belief exalt the innerness of the ‘individual’, but also the phenomena of life that are shown to be capable of transformation into something of ultimate value through our experience of them.  

It is hard to flesh out this definition without reference to the practice that is integrally related to it, almost its ‘sacrament’ – notably, that of creativity, especially as embodied in Romantic and post-Romantic notions of ‘epiphanic art’.  In particular, we find exemplified here the idea of a ‘work’ whose outcome cannot be foreseen prior to its accomplishment – hence, the artist’s protestations as to their song/poem etc. not serving to articulate any preconceived message.  Linked to this, we find the value attached to the particularity of the work – hence, the importance of originality.

Expressivist individualism is the application of this notion of ‘creativity’ as a paradigm or model to the whole of one’s life.  Life as a whole is seen as the potential expression of a unique inner self; one’s crucial decisions and whole way of life proceed, ideally, out of a commitment to some inner purpose that is uniquely one’s own, and a value attaches above all to its singularity.

All this is rarely articulated at a theoretical level.  For many, such notions form part of those ideational underpinnings of their everyday lives, the bedrock of their moral commonsense.  For all their inescapably mystical/ideological nature, people rarely question them.  We don’t as a rule question those most fundamental of our ideas which we can’t think beyond, and which determine our thinking about everything else.  An appreciation of their particularity would require of us a degree of de-familiarization and the capacity, as it were, to catch a glimpse of ourselves in the eyes of the cultural other.  This is the exploit we expect of a social anthropologist, the trick we see pulled off by a Mary Douglas, turning an eye recently acculturated in the ways of a tribal people on ritual practices of the North London middle classes, and describing in mystical and religious terms practices that would normally strike us as too banal to be worthy of comment.  But it is a perspective also perhaps available to social and cultural revolutionaries.  At all events, the following extract from a prose ‘novel’ by the

Surrealist Andre Breton, dating from the 1920s, offers the best expression known to me the expressivist individualist mindset.

Over and above the various prejudices I acknowledge, the affinities I feel, the attractions I succumb to, the events which occur to me and to me alone – over and above a sum of movements I am conscious of making, of emotions I alone experience – I strive, in relation to other men, to discover the nature, if not the necessity, of my difference (‘différenciation’) from them.  Is it not precisely to the degree I become conscious of this difference that I shall have the revelation (‘je me révélerai’) of what I alone have been put on this earth to do, what unique message I alone may bear so as to have to answer for it with my life (‘pour ne pouvoir répondre de son sort que sur ma tête’)

This is almost the definition of expressivist individualism placed in the mouth of a first-person narrator.  However, the mystical nature of the language de-familiarizes what would otherwise strike us as the almost commonplace character of the sentiments expressed.  It was, of course, the explicit intention of the surrealists to de-familiarize the familiar.  But in the context of the novel as a whole – and the surrealist oeuvre more generally – this mystical language of ‘message’ and ‘revelation’ also has a programmatic function, being widely used by the surrealists in reference to the operation of poetic creativity.  We find in this passage an almost total convergence of real-life aspiration with the ideal of poetic creation exemplified by the text we hold in our hands.  In this case, therefore, it requires no great stretch of the imagination to see life patterning itself on art!   

I hope to have said enough about expressivist individualism and its construction of self (i.e. as ‘Self’) for my understanding of both those notions to be clear to the reader.

Now – to return to my own 4am revelation – what would be the implications of the construction of self as Self for our attitudes to ‘insecurity’ and ‘uncertainty’?

On a commonsense level, an absolute commitment to self-realization and to the personal freedom that it requires are hardly conducive to a sense of security or certainty.  So much seems self-evident, and is attested, I would, argue by those feelings of rootlessness and loss of meaning that seem, on general agreement, to be a feature of the modern condition.  Freedom in personal relationships, the decay of the family, the erosion of the institutional structures – such things are surely the price we pay.

In the more philosophical terms of the analysis developed hitherto, I would argue that, through the construction of self as Self, i.e. as something essentially inward and unique to the individual, precisely those social, cultural, and institutional elements that root us in space – and, more importantly, time – are stripped away.  By according a privileged reality to the Self, we de-realize those aspects of our world that we share with everyone else.  This de-realization is precisely what we see in Becker’s attempt to see ‘customs, traditions, and laws that we have designed to hep us feel part of something bigger and longer-lasting than mere human life’ as the ‘immortality projects’ of individuals desiring to ‘break free of death’s gravitational pull’.  Indeed, his view is only comprehensible at all when we limit our self-identification to the relatively narrow compass of the Self, as defined above.  Yet, given that is precisely what increasing numbers of us are doing, Becker’s shockingly individualist conclusions may have come to seem self-evident.

I would add that, on my own – as opposed to B.’s – analysis, the ‘impermanence’ and ‘transience’ he fears may be an inescapable aspect, not so much of ‘life’ itself, as of the world as it presents itself to the subject identified with Self.  It is no surprise that the world of those devoted to freedom and fulfilment should turn out to be a world haunted by insecurity and uncertainty. 

Now the Surrealists, clear-sighted revolutionaries as they undoubtedly were, embraced that world with eyes wide open.  Yet, now their aspirations have become commonplace, just part of the air we breathe, I am not sure their effective spiritual successors are aware of the Faustian bargain they have inadvertently struck, or that has inadvertently been struck by past generations on their behalf, so that a consciousness of insecurity as a moral choice as somehow been lost to view.  One aspires to freedom and self-fulfilment, and unwittingly suffers the inevitable insecurities that come in its train.  Yet, the more those securities elude the grasp, the more frenetically they are sought.  The world of expressivist individualism will of necessity be a world characterized by an anguished relation to insecurity and uncertainty. 

A Christian antidote?

So, what is the antidote that works?  Evidently not, I would say, to accept the ‘impermanence’ of the world, and disengage from our projects.  Rather it would begin by jettisoning expressivist individualism and the exposure of the construct of Self for what it is – a construct specific to a contemporary religious worldview.  But where would that take us?  And (the same question we asked of Burkeman) is there anything we can offer in its place?  Evidently, we are in need of a broader, less individualist construct of self as the basis of a broader engagement with reality.  But where might such a thing be found?  After all, we can hardly just carry on without!

This leads me to ask, inevitably, whether Christianity might have something distinctive to offer here – needless to say, not one of the avenues that B. chooses to explore.

One reason to look in that direction is that my critique of the ‘Watts’-type expressivist individualist philosophy is already grounded, I would argue, in a broadly biblical anthropology, and a broadly biblical style of critique, based on that anthropology – namely, the critique of what we might unfashionably call idolatry.  The essence of both the anthropology and the critique that goes with it is that – whatever Buddhists may tell you – there is no moral alternative to ‘attachment’ and, in a broader sense – to ‘self’.  Rather, the important thing is to have the right ‘attachment’ and the right ‘self’: the intensest possible attachment of the broadest imaginable self.

Before going any further, what I do not mean to propose in the following paragraphs as a Christian alternative response to uncertainty and insecurity of the human condition, is the idea that we take refuge in the absolute certainty and security of a life that awaits us after death, and can thus afford to disinvest in the current world of impermanence.

Aside from whether the Christian hope can be cashed out in this way, I personally just don’t find any spiritual consolation in it – nor do I think it is particularly helpful or conducive to the good life.

What I propose instead is that we being instead with Old Testament responses to the notion of human transience and impermanence – especially in the Psalms, which have been the backbone of Jewish and Christian liturgies alike.

Coping with impermanence in the Psalms

References to mortal transience are on every page – some of them taken up by countless adaptations and imitations in later Western literature.

As for mortals, their days are like grass: they flourish like a flower of the field;/For the wind passes over it, and it is gone, and its place knows it no more.

Nor should we assume the psalmist is here speaking only of the foolish and the wicked:

When we look at the wise, they die;/ …. Mortals cannot abide in their pomp;/they are like the animals that perish.

***

Juxtaposed almost invariably with such evocations of impermanence, we find reference to the eternity of the god to whom the psalmist addresses his worship:

Your throne is established from of old;/You are from everlasting.

Very often, it is not simply the eternity of God’s being that such passages evoke, but His ‘steadfast love’ and ‘faithfulness’ – in short, the timelessness of a unilateral bond in which the faithful Israelite stands as a dependent.  To take just one such example of this juxtaposition (and there are many), the lines from Ps.103 just cited above (‘As for mortals, they are as grass ….’) lead immediately into the following:

But the steadfast love of the Lord is from everlasting to everlasting on those who fear Him, and His righteousness to children’s children/To those who keep his covenant/and remember to do his commandments.

God’s steadfast love and faithfulness can be manifested in quite specific deeds of power and favour accomplished for the people in the past, such as are retold at length by certain narrative Psalms. It is implied that a God who once acted so miraculously, and so faithfully, in furtherance of His plans, can be depended upon, whatever the travails of the psalmist’s present, to bring about their ultimate accomplishment at some time in the future. That eventual fulfilment can take the political and eschatological form of a future restoration of Zion, often under a messianic king of David’s line to whom all nations will be subject; or else, in the case of the psalmist’s personal suffering, some more immediate vindication – always, in this case, within, and not beyond, his own mortal existence (‘I believe that I shall see the goodness of the Lord in the land of the living./’)

Neither of these possibilities, however, quite seems to plumb the depths of the psalmist’s existential hope. This seems somehow to reside in the steadfast love itself, rather than in the various possibilities (i.e. restoration of Zion or victory over personal enemies) through which the psalmist imagines that love as being effectively demonstrated.

Here I come to the heart of what I want to say – something quite hard to poinpoint, let alone put into words. The idea of a covenant faithfulness that is actualized in the case of the Almighty (however inadequately reciprocated by his chosen people) points us to the eternal nature of the One whose Word stands firm, and to the sense in which He stands at the origin of, and so beyond, our space and time as creator and sustainer of all that is. At the same time, the psalmist would have us believe that such a transcendent God has somehow entered into relationship with His people in history. In other words, the focus of so many passages on divine ‘faithfulness and steadfast love’ carries with it the claim that the time-less has entered into relation with the time-bound. This is obviously hard to get one’s mind around. But however we seek to deal with it philosophically, there is one implication of such a claim that appears inescapeable. The mere fact of the possibility of such a relationship with the eternal confers a potentially eternal value to the time-bound object such as to render trivial by comparison any other circumstances of its existence in place and time. This appears to me to be the sentiment behind those famous words of Ps. 63: Because Your steadfast love is better than life.

Thus the psalmist perceives ‘himself’ as somehow belonging within a collective religious project defined by this engagement of the eternal in the timebound and the impermanent. On the one hand, he is struck by the impermanence of things as they exist intrinsically, in and for themselves; on the other, by the ultimate significance lent them by the project which is that of God’s glory. Those transient things shine, as it were, in a reflected light, as a solitary window in an otherwise darkening townscape blazes out in a ray of the setting sun. Here is a classic case of where the ‘self’ constituted through identification with the broader collective project of ‘Israel’ – that project of God’s steadfast love which serves His ultimate glorification – becomes, in the psalmist’s view so enormous and encompassing that the question of the survival of the individual subject (after death) dwindles into insignificance by comparison – like a candle in the full sun at midday, or rock pools before the incoming tide.  It would be hard to find a better instance of the relative solidity and durability of a ‘self’ founded in a reality transcending the more immediate concerns of the ego. This may also be a model of how we could think of the immortality of Christian ‘souls’ in Christ.

***

There are, however, not infrequent passages in the Psalms where a concern with individual death and transience breaks through. Yet it is always in one circumstance, and assumes the same characteristic expression. According to the Psalms, the natural and ordinate response of a creature aware of its being the object of God’s steadfast love and favour is always acknowledgement and praise of Him:

O Lord my God, I shall give thanks to you for ever.

But this inevitably leads the psalmist to pose, from time to time, the question of the still faithful souls descended into Sheol. What of them, and the obligation of praise they might be imagined to owe their creator?  The question evokes a consistent, intriguing, if not ambivalent, response.  On the one hand, the psalmist seems unable to conceive of the possibility of the soul’s post mortem existence – i.e. as something capable of greater conscious agency than dust or shadow.  On the other, this impossibility (or rather perhaps inconceivability) is, as it were, outweighed by a still more overbearing theological refusal to countenance the idea that anything owed to God’s glory should be denied – in other words, that due praise should, in defiance of His glory, be reduced to silence. Hence, the occurrence of passages such as the following:

What profit is there in my death, if I go down to the pit?/Will the dust praise you? Will it tell of your faithfulness?

Or:

Is your steadfast love declared in the grave? Or your faithfulness in Abaddon?/Are your wonders known in the darkness? Or your saving help in the land of forgetfulness?

How are we to interpret such questions? As purely rhetorical? On the face of it, I think, yes. In the first case, the anticipated response would seem to be: ‘None’ and ‘Of course not’. In the second, probably: ‘No’, ‘No’ and ‘No’. Yet the evident depth of the psalmist’s bewilderment and dejection, at least in the case of Ps. 88 (that most despairing of psalms), where the facts of the situation appear to offer no more positive outcome – all of this coupled with the very insistence of his interrogations – perhaps suggest, that while appearing to close a door, he nevertheless holds it slightly ajar. Certainly, this implied ‘No’ is an incredulous one, the silence of death a theological paradox.

***

In the light of everything I have argued hitherto about the response to impermanence in the psalms, I shall turn, at last, briefly to the New Testament, and Jesus’ words of response to a representative of the Sadducees, who ‘said there was no resurrection’ (Matt. 22.23).  There is no doubt that Jesus’ answer refutes the Sadducean position. But what strikes me as particularly interesting here, and highly relevant to what we have been saying, is the nature of his answer. We might have expected that it would lay claim to some established dogma – as the Church generally does today, and the Pharisees no doubt did before them. However, Jesus’ actual answer seems strangely in line with the position we have observed in the psalmist. It rests on the troublingly trans-temporal status of the relationship between an eternal God (the ‘I am’ of Moses’ encounter in the burning bush) and the evidently human, and therefore mortal, nature of the patriarchs of whom He IS the God.

Jesus answered them ….  ‘… And as for the resurrection of the dead, have you not read what was said to you by God. “I am the God of Abraham, the God of Isaac, and the God of Jacob”?  He is God not of the dead, but of the living.’

To my mind, this expresses the existential basis of the psalmist’s hope – the way that it seems to rest on the steadfast love and faithfulness of God and nothing else. Where the eternal is somehow in relationship with (‘is God of’) a human object, how can that object of eternal sollicitude cease to be? This takes the pslamists question, and answers with the affirmative:

Will the dust praise you?

.

Psalm 30[a]

I will exalt you, Lord,
    for you lifted me out of the depths
    and did not let my enemies gloat over me.
Lord my God, I called to you for help,
    and you healed me.
You, Lord, brought me up from the realm of the dead;
    you spared me from going down to the pit.

Sing the praises of the Lord, you his faithful people;
    praise his holy name.
For his anger lasts only a moment,
    but his favor lasts a lifetime;
weeping may stay for the night,
    but rejoicing comes in the morning.

When I felt secure, I said,
    “I will never be shaken.”
Lord, when you favored me,
    you made my royal mountain[c] stand firm;
but when you hid your face,
    I was dismayed.

To you, Lord, I called;
    to the Lord I cried for mercy:
“What is gained if I am silenced,
    if I go down to the pit?
Will the dust praise you?
    Will it proclaim your faithfulness?
10 Hear, Lord, and be merciful to me;
    Lord, be my help.”

11 You turned my wailing into dancing;
    you removed my sackcloth and clothed me with joy,
12 that my heart may sing your praises and not be silent.
    Lord my God, I will praise you forever.

                .

This entry was posted in Review. Bookmark the permalink.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *